THE CONTEMPORARY LAW OF SUPERIOR
RESPONSIBILITY
American
Journal of International Law v.93, no. 3, July 1999
By
Ilias Bantekas(1)
“x
x x.
II.
Legal Nature of the Doctrine
The
Existence of a Duty
People
who fail to prevent or punish their subordinates' illegal acts are liable under
the doctrine of command responsibility. Accordingly, the doctrine does not
address actions but omissions. Most systems of criminal law punish unlawful
positive conduct, thus requiring the commission of an act. Exceptionally,
common law jurisdictions recognize personal liability for omissions only where
a specific duty is prescribed either by statute or by the common law.(22)
Such duties include those arising from familial,(23)
contractual,(24) doctor-patient(25)
and voluntary assumption of care(26) relationships, as well as the
duty to avert injurious consequences arising from one's own fault.(27)
Express
formulations of duties pertaining to commanders are found in Article 86 of
Geneva Protocol I (1977), Article 6 of the International Law Commission's (ILC)
Draft Code of Crimes Against the Peace and Security of Mankind,(28)
Article 7(3) of the ICTY Statute,(29) Article 6(3) of the ICTR(30)
Statute and Article 28(2) of the ICC statute.(31)
All these instruments give commanders the responsibility to prevent their
subordinates from violating the laws of war and the responsibility to punish
their subordinates if the laws of war are violated.
X
x x.
III.
Subordination
Establishing
a Superior-Subordinate Relationship
The
required three elements of the crime have developed over time. Depending on the
source from which authority is acquired, the existence of a
superior-subordinate relationship can be established in two independent ways,
de jure and de facto. The most obvious means for the assumption of power is
through official delegation of command from a pertinent office. This authority
evinces de jure command over other persons. However, a position of command
cannot be determined by reference to formal status alone.(47)
In the absence of a formal grant of authority, the accused must actually be
found to possess the right to control subordinates.(48)
Mere authority to control actions of others does not preclude a finding of
command responsibility.(49)
Such
de jure command may be determined by reference to the position of the accused
"in the overall organization, with a view to determining [his/her]
institutional functions."(50) Primarily, therefore, the nature
of the "organization" must be discerned, and specifically its
capacity to delegate further authority. Formal executive structures, such as
state entities, usually vest such authority by passing legislative acts, which
provide evidence of de jure command. For example, the Akayesu case
involved allegations of incitement and complicity of a Rwandan local civilian
official for the actions of others resulting in genocide against the Tutsi
population residing in his commune. The ICTR Trial Chamber adduced that
according to Rwandese law, Akayesu's position as burgomaster placed him as (1)
the head of the communal administration; (2) the officier de l'état, and
(3) the person responsible for maintaining and restoring the peace.(51)
That was sufficient to establish Akayesu's de jure authority as a necessary
element of his conviction for the crime of genocide.
De
jure power determines one's competence and jurisdiction in the sense that
authority to take action or intervention is confined to a pre-defined field
beyond which there exists no competency and subsequently no liability.(52)
Nonetheless, de jure command is not the best determinant of actual authority,
since problems of identification will arise when legislation is absent,
obscure, or, even if available, it inadequately describes one's actual
functions and the amount of authority actually exercised.(53)
The Sources of de Jure Command
The Sources of de Jure Command
Both
the civilian and military components of every state's machinery constitute
integral national defense structures. This hierarchical model is built upon a
vertical scale, which seeks to effectively filter the dictates of the
decision-makers down to the soldier on the battlefield. This vertical scale
assumes four general stages of command. The first is policy command. That
involves the power to determine policy objectives and, consequently, the power
to commit or withdraw a state's armed forces. This is exercised by state leaders
either personally or collectively.(54) The second is the phase of
strategic command. The highest military authorities are responsible to produce
a viable military plan to achieve policy command objectives. These plans are
usually drawn up by the Joint Chiefs of Staff in conjunction with other senior
government officials, and require authorization by those with policy command
authority before implementation.(55)
When
the plan is finally authorized, it is passed down the chain of command for
implementation on the battlefield. This is undertaken at the third operational
level by senior military officers who command midlevel groupings of forces, mainly
in the form of corps or divisions. Senior military officers do not issue orders
directly to troops, but direct the commanders of smaller groupings.(56)
At the end of the scale, tactical commanders exercise direct command over
troops. At this level, persons of any rank may assume tactical command, since
even a senior private can head a unit whose other superiors have been
incapacitated from battle.(57)
This
structure is divided differently in cooperative international military actions.
In the recent United Nations command structure,(58)
for example, authority for both policy and strategic command is vested in and
exercised by the Security Council and, to a very limited degree, by the
Secretary-General.(59) A UN operation consists of a
Force Commander who exercises operational command over contingents provided by
member states.(60) For the duration and purposes of
the specific operation military personnel under the Force Commander are
"international personnel," although they remain in their national
service.(61) In practice, Force Commanders have been granted
"full authority" over their forces and have as a result been held
"operationally responsible" for their performance.(62)
De Facto Command and the Concept of Control
De Facto Command and the Concept of Control
If
liability for the acts of others is established through the element of
authority over subordinates, it follows that the mere existence of such
authority, whether acquired de jure or de facto, renders one a superior for the
purposes of Article 7(3) of the ICTY Statute.(63)
While instances of de facto command authority are a phenomena of civil warfare,
their existence was contemplated even in the context of inter-state conflicts.
The United States Military Tribunal in the Sadaiche case pointed out
that "superior means superior in capacity and power to force a certain
act. It does not mean superiority only in rank [since] it could easily happen
in an illegal enterprise that the captain guides the major, in which case the
captain could not be heard to plead superior orders."(64)
In that case, the accused, a commanding officer of a POW camp, was held liable
because he was led to acquiescence by his "more powerful adjutant."(65)
Power to force a certain act inevitably involves the power to demand and an
actual capacity to impose obeisance. Therefore, usurpation of authority
contrary to national law would not prevent an individual from being convicted
on the basis of command responsibility for international crimes committed if
the person had de facto authority.
This
view was upheld during the preparatory conferences that led to Protocol I
(1977), where reference to "commanders" in Article 87 encompassed
persons in command "at the highest level to leaders with only a few men
under their command."(66) This consistent irrelevance of
rank in attributing superior responsibility indicates that the international
law-making institutions look to actual and effective control,(67)
rather than formality.(68) Article 87 of Geneva Protocol I
(1977) extends the legal obligations of commanders beyond troops under their
command to cover in addition "other persons under their control."(69)
This obligation is applicable to superiors at all levels of command.(70)
If the case were different, superiors with ample means to intervene in crimes
committed by troops under their control, but not under their command, would be
fully justified in being passive. Accordingly, the concept of
"command" is not the only operative term for ascribing command
liability, as the text of Article 87 extends the obligations of commanders to
troops under their control.(71)
Evidence
of de facto control requires proof of a superior-subordinate relationship.(72)
The elebii judgment recognized that the accused, Delali, by special
authorization of his local War Presidency, was authorized to negotiate and
conclude important contracts and agreements on their behalf, but noted that he
never acquired any status which placed him in a hierarchy of authority creating
a superior and subordinate relationship.(73)
His function was described as one of "co-ordination." This consisted
of negotiating agreements for the President. That rendered him influential, but
it did not create a superior-subordinate relationship.(74)
Control in this sense must be effective. However, partial control will suffice
when superiors have not exercised their potential for full control, in an
attempt to evade personal liability.(75)
Similarly, when troops not normally under one's command are assigned to
another's forces, they too are considered to be forces under the special
commander.(76)
A
superior-subordinate relationship finally requires a chain of command.(77)
Thus, tactical commanders exercise "direct subordination" over troops
assigned to them, while commanders of occupied territory (executive commanders)
enjoy "indirect subordination" over a civilian mob which they are
under a duty to prevent from committing crimes against other civilians in the
territory occupied.(78) Since a chain of command is a
prerequisite for the exercise of superior authority, it follows that one cannot
be termed a superior without corresponding subordinates.(79)
That is why staff officers, who, irrespective of their rank, do not command
troops, are only responsible when their participation in the delivery and
execution of criminal orders is proven.(80)
The sole exception to the requirement of subordination is the case of executive
commanders in occupied territory.(81) Their responsibility is coextensive
with their area of command,(82) and is not dependent on the
persons they command or the exercise of effective control. They are responsible
for the behavior of the occupation forces as well as the civilian population in
the occupied territory.(83)
X
x x.
V.
Types of Command And Extent of Liability
Superior
authority necessitates a chain of command.(120)
While operational command supposes vested authority over units linked to the
operational superior through the leader of each unit, tactical command refers
to a state of actual control over a defined number of subordinates. Command and
control are thus not the same thing but are evidently inter-related.(121)
The following is an analysis of the necessary and reasonable measures expected
of operational, tactical and POW camp commanders, as well as the extent of
their liability in accordance with either the people they command or control,
or the territory they occupy.
Operational Commanders
Operational Commanders
The
Yamashita case is a fine example of operational command. The accused,
Supreme Military Commander of the Japanese Imperial Army on the Philippines and
Governor of the islands, was charged with breaching his duty to control his
troops, thereby permitting them to perpetrate numerous and large-scale
offenses.(122) Despite his de jure command,
Yamashita, who assumed his post only eleven days before the invasion by United
States forces,(123) ordered a partial evacuation.
He then split the remainder of the Japanese forces into three separate fighting
units, ceding full command of two, and commanding the other himself.(124)
Contrary to his orders, the evacuation did not occur, and Yamashita was left
isolated in a remote mountainous region, apparently lacking communications with
his headquarters and the two other commanders.(125)
Yamashita's
conviction was upheld for acts of troops beyond his de facto control, on the
ground that operational command responsibility cannot be ceded for the purposes
of the doctrine of command responsibility even though the specific aspects of
such command are actually ceded to others.(126)
This rule, referred to as the "delegation principle," is recognized
as a general principle of criminal law.(127)
It strains the mind to consider the possibility of upholding criminal
responsibility in cases where both de facto control is missing and de jure
command was already ceded for military purposes and not for the purpose of
escaping criminal responsibility.(128) Certainly, it must have seemed to
the Supreme Court that authority was delegated for the purpose of evading
responsibility which raised the risks of crime.(129)
Command responsibility cannot be avoided.
The
test followed in subsequent cases strikes a reasonable balance between
knowledge of subordinate offenses and material capacity to act. Thus, the
murderous onslaught of Japanese forces on the Chinese city of Nanking under the
command of General Matsui, rendered the General liable even though he issued
instructions to abide by the laws of war, albeit lukewarm instructions at best,
because he had every opportunity and ability to act to prevent and stop the
crimes.(130) It is now well established that operational
commanders must exercise the full potential of their authority to avert war
crimes. They will not be exonerated in cases of non-assertive orders or failure
to supervise their implementation.(131)
Similarly, the United States Military Tribunal in the High Command case
demanded a "personal dereliction," for the application of the failure
to act doctrine,(132) indicating that command
responsibility was not viewed as a form of vicarious or strict liability.
Personal dereliction in this sense is tantamount to a failure to supervise.
That supervision is commensurate with the exercise of actual control in the
given circumstances. Knowledge of every aspect of operational command is not
required.(133) Rather, commanders may
lawfully, within reason, presume that "details entrusted to subordinates
will be legally executed."(134)
Executive Commanders
Executive Commanders
Executive
or occupation commanders are those individuals vested by the occupying state
with supreme governing authority in the occupied territory. The difference
between operational and executive commanders is that while the former are
responsible for the acts of people under their command or control, the latter
are accountable within the territory they occupy to assure that the rights of
civilians and POWs therein are fully protected. In the case of executive
commanders, subordination is unimportant, their responsibility is co-extensive
with their appointed command structure.(135)
This responsibility cannot be limited, even by a commander's own state's
legislation.(136) Since executive superiors are
not bound under the rule of subordination, they have a duty to prevent and
punish crimes which involve auxiliary or allied forces stationed within their
area of command.(137) A similar duty exists in cases
of inter-communal rivalry.(138) Commanders are also obliged to enforce
discipline in related events in order to protect both local majorities and
minorities.
In
cases where executive commanders also perform operational tasks, they must
nonetheless be aware of any occurrences within their territory, even if they
are not present.(139) Hence, the exercise also of
operational command does not absolve them from their executive command
obligations. Acquisition of information can be achieved by demanding constant
and reliable appraisal of all pertinent facts.(140)
This generally involves establishing an effective reporting system which would
ensure delivery of adequate and up to date information to the commander.(141)
The duty of executive commanders to protect and care for the welfare of
civilians is a strict responsibility element in the actus reus
definition of their command responsibility.(142)
Persons Entrusted with the Care of Prisoners
Persons Entrusted with the Care of Prisoners
According
to a basic principle of military law and practice, once under captivity,
prisoners become subordinates to the captor commanders,(143)
and are deemed to be in the hands of the captor state.(144)
Since Hague Convention IV (1907) POWs are customarily offered humane treatment.(145)
Therefore, responsibility for their treatment rests with government officials,
operational officers in command of formations who are holding the prisoners, as
well as officials in departments concerned with prisoner welfare and any other
civilian or military official being in direct and immediate control of
prisoners.(146) It seems unreasonable, however,
to hold government officials responsible without requiring proof of knowledge
and a capacity to act.(147) However, rules that hold the
Head of government and minister in charge of prisoner affairs responsible are
reasonable, since these officials' duties are to acquire knowledge and act
accordingly.(148)
While
the liability of POW camp commanders is based on direct subordination,(149)
the responsibility of departmental officials charged with prisoner affairs can
be justified only if assimilated to that of staff officers who exercise neither
command nor control authority. They would incur responsibility only when there
is proof of direct participation.(150) Since camp commanders are
entrusted with the care of prisoners, subordination of any kind is irrelevant;
their authority and responsibility extends over the entire institution and all
its personnel.(151)
X
x x.
VII.
The Duty to Act
Article
7(3) of the ICTY Statute, Article 6(3) of the ICTR Statute, Article 86(2) of
Geneva Protocol I and Article 28(1)(a) of the ICC statute firmly establish the
existence of a duty to prevent and a duty to punish the crimes of subordinate persons.(190)
They constitute distinct and independent legal obligations,(191)
and this is further affirmed by the use of the disjunctive "or" in
Article 86(2) of Geneva Protocol I. These articles necessarily suggest a
further "duty to control."
The Duty to Prevent
The Duty to Prevent
Article
86(2) of Geneva Protocol I and Article 7(3) of the ICTY Statute expressly
establish a duty to prevent at the moment subordinates "are going (or
"are about") to commit a crime."(192)
The duty to prevent commences upon the preparation or planning of an offense by
subordinates. Commanders are even responsible for failure to prevent if they
fail to take into account factors such as the age, training or similar elements
that point to obvious conclusions regarding the likelihood that such crimes
would be committed.(193) The abundance of information
clearly indicating a massacre at two Palestinian refugee camps in Lebanon that
was available to the Israeli Chief-of-Staff and the Defense Minister rendered
them "indirectly responsible" under a test of anticipated foreseeability
lacking direct intent.(194) Their duty, according to a
subsequent investigative report of a governmental commission, was to recognize
the potential danger and to prevent the killings by doing everything in their
power to stop them.(195)
Superiors
successfully discharge their duty to prevent subordinate crimes when they
employ every means in their power to do so.(196)
This also involves pointing out objections to a criminal plan, even if the
accused has no further authority to intervene.(197)
Reference to a duty to prevent has been limited thus far in the ICTY and ICTR.(198)
In the Akayesu case, Trial Chamber I pointed out that whether a superior
had the power to prevent the crimes of subordinates is irrelevant if the
superior did not attempt to do so.(199)
However, failure to condemn incendiary statements uttered at an already formed
gathering would not be tantamount to approval.(200)
This conclusion should be approached with some caution since it arose in the
unique circumstances of the Rwandan massacres. It may not reflect a statement
of general law,(201) but may pertain to civilian
superiors whose authority to intervene is unclear.(202)
The Duty to Punish
The Duty to Punish
A
superior's "duty to punish" arises after the commission of an
offense. It is predicated upon offenses by others which have already occurred,
not future offenses.(203) Punishment is, therefore,
intended to deter the commission of future offenses. This duty to punish is
distinct from a commander's preventive duty. For that reason, failure to
prevent recurrence of future crimes is another aspect of the "duty to
punish."(204) Failure to punish, as a form of
command responsibility, is a species of imputed responsibility for an omission
and is neither akin to the common law concepts of "accessory after the
fact"(205) nor "misprision of
felony."(206) The duty to punish does not
require a pre-existing relationship to those who perpetrated the offenses, as
this would have been part of the incumbent superior's preventive duty at the
time the offenses occurred. Thus even persons who assume command after such
offenses have taken place are under a duty to investigate and punish the
offenders.
Since
it will not always be feasible to initiate judicial proceedings, especially in
the midst of military operations, the only available option may be to commence
adequate investigations and report the findings to superiors. Tolerating
criminal conduct, as evidenced by the failure to punish, is tantamount to
acquiescence.(207) When superiors are physically
unable to prosecute, arrest, incarcerate or in any way discipline a
subordinate, they must try to discover whether crimes were committed and, if
they are ongoing, to find ways to stop them.(208)
If a crime is discovered, they must refer the case to the appropriate judicial
or prosecutorial authorities, or to any other competent
authority.(209)
In
conclusion, a superior should be held responsible for failing to take all
measures that are "within his material possibility."(210)
Trial Chamber I in the elebii case correctly disagreed with the ILC's
demand that both legal and material possibility to take appropriate measures be
present. The Chamber took the position that only the latter is required.(211)
It would be absurd for superiors to claim that they were not legally entitled
to prevent an act of genocide when they were materially capable of doing
so.
x x x.
x x x.
VIII. Conclusion
The
interplay between humanitarian and criminal law at the international level
suggests that the best approach to the doctrine of command responsibility
should be through the concept of control. Assessment of de jure command must
not mislead tribunals as to the accused's actual authority. This in no way
widens the ambit of command responsibility, since it follows the established
principle of international law that actual power is linked to responsibility.
The interest of the state in the protection of its officials should not
obstruct the development of these norms. If the international community
seriously intends to combat gross human rights violations it has to do so
irrespective of particular states interests in order to attain the interests of
the broader international society. An ideal ground would be to strengthen the
international criminal justice system in ways that would not jeopardize national
security interests by applying the law uniformly regardless of the state or
region involved.
Increasingly,
the need for review or re-assessment of humanitarian norms will arise,
especially when cases come before tribunals, such as the ICTY and ICTR. Then,
factors like the unpredictable nature of civil warfare will demand adaptation
of established rules to fit these new circumstances. Since Yamashita,
the law of command responsibility has moved to new realms. The question now
seems to center around the issue of subordination and control, while fierce
debate exists on the applicable mens rea standard. A presumption of
knowledge in cases of notorious and widespread criminality is an emerging rule
of customary law. The traditional "failure to act" doctrine is too
limited to cover situations in which a superior's negligent or deliberate
inactivity to control his or her troops causes crimes to be committed by them
when under another superior's command.
Furthermore,
command responsibility should not be overlooked when examining the nature of a
mixed conflict. The ICJ in the Nicaragua case determined that when an
intervening state gives "direct and critical combat support" to an
insurgent force and insurgent operations reflect "strategy and tactics
wholly devised" by the intervening state, then an agency relationship is
established.(222) Indeed, despite the
inconsistent understanding and application of the Nicaragua test by the
various ICTY Chambers,(223) in cases where an agency
relationship is found to exist it is not far-fetched to consider the military
or political leaders of the intervening state to be individually responsible
for certain acts of their agent "subordinates."
The
obvious strategy for any prosecution for a breach of humanitarian law is to
choose one that provides evidence of the accused's direct participation in the
crime, such as ordering or inciting the actions, preserving command liability
as a second option. In any event, however, prosecutorial authorities should not
hesitate to indict persons who, while in positions of authority and with
knowledge of subordinate criminality, intentionally or negligently fail to
prevent or punish those persons who directly participated in the crime.
X
x x.”